Plato (c. 427–347 BC) and Aristotle (c. 384–322 BC) both posited first cause arguments, though each had certain notable caveats. In The Laws (Book X), Plato posited that all movement in the world and the Cosmos was "imparted motion". This required a "self-originated motion" to set it in motion and to maintain it. In Timaeus, Plato posited a "demiurge" of supreme wisdom and intelligence as the creator of the Cosmos.
Aristotle argued against the idea of a first cause, often confused with the idea of a "prime mover" or "unmoved mover" in his Physics and Metaphysics. Aristotle argued in favor of the idea of several unmoved movers, one powering each celestial sphere, which he believed lived beyond the sphere of the fixed stars, and explained why motion in the universe (which he believed was eternal) had continued for an infinite period of time. Aristotle argued the atomist's assertion of a non-eternal universe would require a first uncaused cause – in his terminology, an efficient first cause – an idea he considered a nonsensical flaw in the reasoning of the atomists.
Like Plato, Aristotle believed in an eternal cosmos with no beginning and no end (which in turn follows Parmenides' famous statement that "nothing comes from nothing"). In what he called "first philosophy" or metaphysics, Aristotle did intend a theological correspondence between the prime mover and a deity; functionally, however, he provided an explanation for the apparent motion of the "fixed stars" (now understood as the daily rotation of the Earth). According to his theses, immaterial unmoved movers are eternal unchangeable beings that constantly think about thinking, but being immaterial, they are incapable of interacting with the cosmos and have no knowledge of what transpires therein. From an "aspiration or desire", the celestial spheres, imitate that purely intellectual activity as best they can, by uniform circular motion. The unmoved movers inspiring the planetary spheres are no different in kind from the prime mover, they merely suffer a dependency of relation to the prime mover. Correspondingly, the motions of the planets are subordinate to the motion inspired by the prime mover in the sphere of fixed stars. Aristotle's natural theology admitted no creation or capriciousness from the immortal pantheon, but maintained a defense against dangerous charges of impiety. (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cosmological_argument)
~ ~ ~
In the previous post, I laid out Philip Goff’s ‘Pan-agentialism’ idea which required that he dispense with Schrödinger’s Cat and Many Worlds, resulting in his adoption of Pilot-wave Theory which included ‘rational matter’.
… the stuff of the
world is rational stuff. Even when
behaving in a predictable way, its behaviour is the result of a rational
impulse, albeit of a very crude kind. As
matter evolves into complex forms, more and more the potential for rational
thought and action begins to flower, blossoming in the reflective consciousness
of a human being able to discern and respond to practical and theoretical
reasons. This is not just matter
changing, but matter maturing, coming to a greater realization of its inherent
rational nature.
The
pan-agentialist world is, by definition, a world that embodies purpose. Crucially, however, purpose in this sense
does not imply design. Aristotle did
believe in some kind of first cause – an ‘unmoved mover’ – but not a beneficent
designer who had crafted the purposes of things. In Aristotle’s worldview, things just had
goal-directed natures, regardless of their origins. Likewise, if matter, in its fundamental
nature, is directed towards reason, then matter has a goal-directed purpose or
nature regardless of whether or not it was designed. It is in this sense that consciousness points
to purpose, as an essential component of the best explanation of the emergence
of experiential understanding.
Goff proposes that we take pan-agentialism
as established (!) and consider it in light of the fine-tuning of physics and,
voila! we discover that the two mutually reinforce each other and reinforce the
reality of purpose. And so he declares
that the laws of physics are fine-tuned not just for life, but also for the
possibility of rational matter achieving a high realization of its nature. That is, fine-tuning and rational matter need
each other; they fit together like a lock and key!
He then launches into a series of Bayesian
arguments for Pan-Agentialism. He had previously argued based on the Likelihood
Principle, that the fine-tuning of physics for life supports the Value-Selection
hypothesis against the Cosmic Fluke Hypothesis.
And now, he uses the same principle saying “the existence of
experiential understanding supports pan-agentialism over our standard scientific
worldview, as it is much more likely that experiential understanding would have
evolved on the former hypothesis than on the latter.”
Goff moves through some cursory discussion
about free will that is uninspiring and need not detain us. He then plunges directly into Theodicy in
order to engage with “does God exist?” He points out that there are many
examples of horrific suffering in Nature, and that, in fact suffering is built
into Natural Selection. He asks “Why would an all-powerful being choose to
bring us into existence through such a gruesome, long-winded, tortuous process
as a game of ‘survival of the fittest’? … why give us bodies that age, get
sick, and fall apart so easily? Why not
instead create immortal, spiritual beings to spend eternity in loving union with
God and with each other?”
He then trots out the usual arguments for review, but
Goff isn’t having it. He writes:
Personally, I am
unconvinced by these proposals. I agree
that there are certain goods we find in the real world – compassion, courage,
adventure, scientific enquiry – that would not exist in a more perfect
world. But it seems to me to massively
reduce the value of these goods if they were brought about through artificially
engineering challenges and difficulties.
Did Goff forget that he just argued for “matter
maturing, coming to a greater realization of its inherent rational nature” and
did he not note that horrific suffering was part and parcel of Natural
Selection?
Of course, Goff has set the argument up to
be a Straw Man – an omnipotent, omniscient god who created the world via fiat –
and who is immoral, in Goff’s opinion, for deliberately creating a world such
as ours. But he slogs on toward the Cosmological argument: without a creator
God, we have no explanation for why the universe came to be nor any explanation
for anything at all. He notes the atheist
response: why does the universe require an explanation, but God gets a free
pass?
· The Kālam Cosmological Argument: The crucial difference between God and the universe is that the universe began to exist whereas God did not. Things that begin to exist require causal explanation, whereas things that are timeless, do not. See: Kalām cosmological argument https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cosmological_argument
· The Contingency Argument: the reason the universe cries out for explanation is that it is contingent, which means that it might not have existed. If something exists but might not have existed, then we need to give some explanation as to why it does exist. God, in contrast, is not contingent; God is a necessary being, a being that has to exist. See Aquinas Argument from contingency: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cosmological_argument
Goff tells us that Cosmological arguments
proceed in two stages. First, the
argument tries to establish that a timeless/necessary being has to exist to
complete the Great Chain of Explanation.
Second, the arguments try to show that this timeless/necessary being
must have the characteristics of the Omni-God: omniscient, omnipotent, and
perfectly good. Goff then makes an
eminently rational remark: “If we are rationally compelled to accept the
existence of a timeless, necessarily existent entity, why not suppose that the
entity is the universe itself, rather than postulating something supernatural
outside of the universe?” Good idea, in my opinion. He then says something
more: “… at best, these arguments prove that the universe’s existence as a spatiotemporal entity is contingent
and began at a finite point in the past.
A possibility rarely considered in these discussions is that the universe,
prior to the Big Bang, existed in a non-spatiotemporal
form. … once we have committed to
the existence of a necessary and timeless foundation of existence, we face a
choice between two theoretical possibilities:
Option 1: The
necessary and timeless foundation of existence is distinct from the universe
and brought the universe into being.
Option 2: The
necessary and timeless foundation of existence became the universe a finite
period of time ago, undergoing a radical change analogous – although obviously
more extreme – to a caterpillar becoming a butterfly.
That is, the basic cosmological argument of
either type merely establishes that a first cause exists, not that it has the
attributes of a theistic god, such as omniscience, omnipotence, and
omnibenevolence.
However, some cosmologists and physicists
argue that a major challenge to the cosmological argument is the nature of
time: The Big Bang theory states that it
(the Big Bang) is the start of both space and time. The claim of the cosmologists
and physicists is that the question "What was there before the
Universe?" becomes meaningless when considering a situation without time. Some
even say that asking what occurred before the Big Bang is like asking what is
north of the North Pole? (Gott III, J.
Richard; Gunn, James E.; Schramm, David N.; Tinsley, Beatrice M. (March 1976).
"Will the Universe Expand Forever?" Scientific American. p. 65.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/24950306).
Getting back to Goff. He notes that Ockham’s razor enters and
eliminates option 1 since option 2 postulates fewer entities. Fine. Goff then brings
to our notice the ideas of Joshua Rasmussen who argues that “the Ultimate
Foundation of all reality cannot involve arbitrary limits. … The Ultimate Foundation, by definition, must
leave nothing to be explained. The
Ultimate Foundation cannot have a certain amount of power, knowledge, and
goodness, whilst not being all-powerful, all-knowing, and perfectly good. For it would then cry out for explanation why
the Ultimate Foundation has precisely that level of power (and not more or
less), that level of knowledge, and that level of goodness – and these
explanatory demands would undermine its putative status to be the point where
explanations come to an end.”
Goff agrees. Arbitrary limits demand explanations. He then
says: “We would still want to know why that maximally perfect exists rather
than the even simpler hypothesis of nothing at all existing… And the Omni-God
hypothesis, even if it is very simple, is not compatible with the data of evil
and suffering. …Those who deny cosmic purpose
cannot explain cosmological fine-tuning, believers in the Omni-God cannot
explain the evil and suffering we find in the world.”
Goff next engages with Theists, sceptical theists,
etc. He allows that the sceptical theists’ way of defusing the problem of evil
is at least somewhat effective: “If God did have a reason for allowing
suffering, would I likely know about it?”
And the answer is “no” because the cognitive gap between humans and God
is so vast that there is no comparison, no way humans could understand any such
reasons. But then, Goff diverts to his
own idea: the ‘Cosmic Sin Intuition.’
That is, “it would be immoral for an all-powerful being to deliberately
create a universe like ours.” He writes:
I cannot rule out
that there might be all sorts of goods and evils I have no clue about, and
maybe if I took them into account, the Cosmic Sin Intuition would lose its
force. But we do have substantial
knowledge of morality, and no reason to think that this knowledge isn’t up to
the task of assessing the Cosmic Sin Intuition.
Following a few desultory feints, he then concludes
that the only rational position to take is to conclude that the Omni-God does
not exist and that “we have very good reason to accept the Cosmic Sin
Intuition. And the Cosmic Sin Intuition entails
that the Omni-God does not exist.” His case is as follows:
The standard line
in the philosophical literature goes as follows:
In the old days, atheist philosophers
tried to demonstrate that God’s existence is logically incompatible with the
existence of evil and suffering, and hence that, given evil and suffering
exist, God’s non-existence can be logically demonstrated. This approach is known as the logical version
of the argument from evil.
Nowadays, most philosophers on both
sides of the debate accept that the logical version of the argument is too
strong. Even if we can’t think of any
good reasons why God might have allowed suffering, we can’t logically
demonstrate that there are no such reasons.
Thus, contemporary atheists tend to argue not that evil and suffering logically
entail God’s non-existence, but rather that they are good evidence for God’s
non-existence.
·
The Cosmic Sin Intuition. It would be immoral for an all-powerful being
to deliberately create a universe like ours.
·
Therefore, if our universe has
a creator, She (sic) is either not all-powerful or not perfectly moral (or
both).
·
Therefore, there is no such
thing as the Omni-God.
By defending the
inherent plausibility of the Cosmic Sin Intuition, we can build a very strong –
although not logically certain – case against the existence of the Omni-God,
one which avoids the sceptical theist critique.
Goff then announces that he is going to
propose “Cosmic Purpose Without God.” That
will be the next post. But before I end this one, I’d like to just mention that
there is an old solution to the problems that Goff and so many others appear to
be struggling with, and not very successfully in my view: the ‘Unity of Being’
theory of 13th century Andalusian mystic and philosopher Muhyiddin Ibn Arabi. But, I will come to that eventually.
"What was there before the Universe?"
ReplyDeleteMy answer: There was Light.
Today the new version of my paper on light appeared on arxiv. Now 32 pages. This time all rewritten for the tangent (instead of cotangent in the previous version) bundle:
The explicit form of the unitary representation of the Poincaré group for vector-valued wave functions (massive and massless), with applications to photon's localization and position operators